昨日394 今日109 合計152863
課題集 ガジュマロ の山

○自由な題名 / 池新
○ゴミ / 池新

★現在『子供』の問題が(感) / 池新
 【1】現在『子供』の問題がたいへん捉えにくく、なにかと不気味なのは、一つには、社会のなかで子供についてのる一定の共通了解事項が成り立たなくなったからである。【2】と同時に「『子供』の問題というのはふつうの問題のように対象化し分析的に捉えていったところであまり意味をなさないからであろう。いまやいろいろな領域で単なる専門家というものは役に立たないといわれ『専門馬鹿』などということばさえ出てくるようになった。【3】けれどもこの問題は、一方で現在ますます専門的知識が必要になっているだけに、どう対処すべきかは簡単ではない。そしてこの場合、なによりも専門的知識の質あるいは在り様が問われることになる。
 【4】永い間、知識とは無知あるいはタブラ・ラサ(白紙)に付け加えられ、積み重ねられたものであり、したがって、より多く知ることがより真理に近づくことだと考えられていた。【5】ところが事実は必ずしもそうとばかりはならずに、ものを多く知ること、多くの知識をもつことによって、かえって私たちの一人一人は在るがままにものを見ることをできなくなるという事態が生ずるようになった。【6】知識が創造的なかたちで働かされなくなるようになったといってもよければ、知識がかえって疎外的に働くようになったといってもいい。こういうことは昔からもなかったわけではない。それは半可通と呼ばれる人たちにはよく見られたことであるけれど、なんといっても現在ほどには問題は尖鋭化、一般化していなかった。【7】現在、こうした場合に必要なことはなにか。それは、専門家であることが、専門的な知識を多くもっていることだけにとどまらず、専門的な知識そのものの弊害を見破り、それに囚われないでいることでなければならないだろう。【8】純粋なあるいは形式的な論理からみれば、そういう作業は折角つくったものをこわすので、なにもしていないに等しいようにみえるかも知れない。しかし、このようなダイナミックな運動をとおしてはじめて、私たちは現実に触れうることになるのである。【9】これはどのような分野についても言いうることだが、とりわけ『子供』の問題に関しては強調されて然るべきだろう。それというのも、『子供』の問題は、囚われない眼で在るがままに見なければならないのに、これほど出来合いの知識によって蔽われている領域はほかにないと思われるからである。【0】そこでは多くの知識が惰性系つまり『見えない制度』と化しやすいのだ。∵
 そのことがもっとも極端なかたちで出てくるのは、『子供』あるいは『教育』の専門家たちによるレッテル貼り(レイベリング)の問題である。そして、専門的な知識が『見えない制度』として拘束的に働くとき、その担い手(エージェント)になるのが職業的専門家である。彼らは職業的専門家として一面ではもちろん有効な働きをするけれど、他面ではそのポスト(地位や職)を保守しその存在意味を示すために、逆にわざわざ仕事をつくり出すことになる。知識や仕事によって自己を不必要に権威づけることになる。その際、もっとも問題なのが、子供たちに対して貼る『非行』や『落ちこぼれ』等々というレッテルなのである。
 大村英昭氏(『非行の社会学』一九八〇年)も言っている。鑑別所によって、子供たちは『非行少年』というレッテルが公式に貼られ、中学や高校の学内試験によって『落ちこぼれ』は公認のものとなるのだが、そのようにひとたび貼られたレッテルは、専門エージェントの権威によってきわめて動かしがたくがしがたくなるだろう。しかも専門エージェントは、自分のところに連れてこられた子供たちになんらかのレッテルを貼らずにはおかないし、またそのための専門的知識に事欠くことはない。そしてしばしば非行少年を救い出すのは、むしろ専門エージェントの権威をもたない人、俗にいう『裸の人間』なのである、と。この裸の人間というのが、専門的知識によって囚われることのない眼をもって相手に接しうる人のことを指すのは言うまでもない。

○All human communities(感) / 池新
All human communities have involved animals. Those present in them always include, for a start, some dogs, with which our association seems to be an incredibly ancient one: we have lived together and helped each other for a long time. But besides them an enormous variety of other creatures, ranging from reindeer to foxes and from elephants to shags, has for ages also been domesticated. Of course they were largely there for use -- for draught and riding, for meat, milk, wool and hides, for feathers and eggs, as catchers of small harmful animals or as aids to fishing and hunting. In principle, it might seem reasonable to expect that these forms of exploitation would have produced no personal or emotional involvement at all. From a position of ignorance, we might have expected that people would view their animals simply as machines. If we impose the sharp distinction made by some philosophers between persons and things, and insist that everything must be considered as simply one or the other, we might have expected that they would be viewed quite clearly as things. But in fact, if people had viewed them like this, the domestication could probably never have worked. The animals, with the best will in the world, could not have reacted like machines. They became tame or domesticated, not just through the fear of violence, but because they were able to form individual bonds with those who tamed them by coming to understand the social signals addressed to them. They learned to obey human beings personally. They were able to do this, not only because the people taming them were social beings, but because they themselves were so as well.
All creatures which have been successfully domesticated are ones which were originally social. They have transferred to human beings the trust and obedience which, in a wild state, they would have developed towards their parents, and in adult life towards the leaders of their pack or herd. There are other, and perhaps equally intelligent, creatures which it is quite impossible to tame, because they simply do not have the natural capacity to respond to social signals in their own species, and therefore cannot reach those which come from outside. The various kinds of wild cat are an impressive example. Even their youngest kittens are quite untamable. Egyptian cats, from which all our domestic ones are descended, are unique among the small-cat group in their friendliness both to humans and to other cats. It is interesting that they do not seem to have been domesticated in Egypt before about 1600 BC, and after that time they quickly became extremely popular. Unless they were only discovered then -- which would be odd -- it seems that there may have been an actual mutation at that point producing a more responsive character.
Cats, however, are notoriously still not friendly or obedient in quite the same way as dogs. Circus people do not usually waste their time trying to train cats. Similarly, there are important differences between the social natures, as well as physical appearances, of horses, donkeys, camels and the like. Both as species and as individuals, they react variously to training; they cannot be treated simply as physical machines. People who succeed well with them do not do so just by some abstract, magical human superiority, but by interacting socially with them -- by attending to them and coming to understand how various things appear from each animal's point of view. To ignore or disbelieve in the existence of that point of view would be fatal to the attempt. The traditional assumption behind the domestication of animals has been that there is something in being a bat, and similarly there is something in being a horse or a donkey, and in being this horse or this donkey. There is not, by contrast, any such experience as being a stone, or a car, or even an airplane. There is no being which could have that experience, and therefore we do not have to bother about this problem.
I am saying that this has been the traditional assumption. Some researchers in animal behaviour today think that it is a false one, and can of course argue against it. My present point is simply that their opinion is a recent and sophisticated one. It is not the view which has been taken for granted during the long centuries in which animals have been domesticated. If an Indian farmer were asked whether the ox being beaten could feel it, that farmer would probably reply, 'Certainly it can, otherwise why would I bother?' A skilled horseman needs to respond to his horse as an individual, to follow the workings of its feelings, to use his imagination in understanding how things are likely to affect it, what frightens it and what attracts it, as much as someone who wants to control human beings needs to do the same thing. Horses and dogs are addressed by name, and are expected to understand what is said to them. Nobody tries this with stones or hammers or airplanes. The treatment of domestic animals has never been impersonal. We can say that they are not 'persons', because that word does generally signify Homo sapiens. But they are certainly not viewed just as things. They are animals, a category which, as far as thinking goes, is closer to human beings than to things.
This point is important because it shows what may seem rather surprising -- a direct capacity in humans for attending to, and to some extent understanding, the moods and reactions of other species. No doubt this capacity is limited. People's harshness makes some of its limitations obvious. But then, similar harshness is also often found in our dealings with other human beings. The question what suffering is being caused is difficult to answer in either case. The indifferent person may not positively know, because there is no willingness to know. Looking at the evidence, however, would give the answer. This seems to be equally true in either case. The reason for overworking an ox or a horse is usually much the same as that for overworking a human slave -- not that one does not believe that they mind it, or supposes that they cannot even notice it, but that one is putting one's own interest first. The treatment of domestic animals resembles that of slaves in being extremely inconsistent and variable. There is not normally a steady, unvarying disregard, such as should follow if one genuinely supposed that the creature did not possess any of the five senses at all, or if one was quite unable to guess what its feeling might be. Disregard is varied by partial occasional kindness, and also by sudden cruelty. And cruelty is something which could have no point for a person who really did not believe the victim to have definite feelings. (There is very little comfort in showing one's anger at a cushion.) Family pigs are often treated with real pride and affection during their lives, they may even be genuinely mourned -- only this will not protect them from being eaten. Horses, Lapp reindeer, and the cattle of the Masai can similarly receive real regard, can be treated as dear companions and personally cherished, can form part of human households in a different way from any machine or material treasure -- only they will still on suitable occasions be killed or otherwise ill-treated if human purposes demand it. But we should notice too a similar unreasonable attitude often appearing in the treatment of human dependants, so that we can scarcely argue that there is no real capacity for sympathy towards the animals. In the treatment of other people, of course, one naturally changes one's mind without reason, and therefore one is constantly disciplined by morality. We know that we must not eat our grandmothers or our children merely because they annoy US. This rule applies less to animals; they have more freedom than people do in this respect. That does not mean that they are taken not to be conscious. Belief in the fact that they do have the five senses and some kind of feelings is essential even for exploiting them successfully.

hsags ウ(鵜)
mutation 突然変異
Lapp ラップ(スカンジナビア半島北部のトナカイ飼養民)の
the Masai マサイ(東アフリカの遊牧民)